Odnośniki
|
[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]
are carried out. On the conduit and container model of information and commu- nication, accountability is often said to require the transparent disclosure of information that makes it available to others. Our focus on communicative action and the epistemic standards it must meet stresses obligations to communicate rather than to disclose. Systems of accountability can come in many forms and serve a variety of purposes. As we see it, systems of accountability are well structured when they protect the legitimate interests and expectations of various parties and provide evidence for the intelli- gent placing and refusal of trust. None of these informational obligations can be discharged without effective communication between the relevant parties, which meets the necessary epistemic norms. 198 Rethinking Informed Consent in Bioethics AFTER RETHI NKI NG: THE POSSI BI LI TY OF CHANGE Although the details are complex, we believe that the everyday views that practitioners, patients and research subjects take of informed consent, and of the reasons why it matters, are closer to the picture that we have offered than they are to the more fashionable views that we have criticised. We see informed consent as a way in which individuals can waive others underlying obligations and expect- ations in specific ways, when they have reason to do so. Informed consent works on the assumption that those individuals and institu- tions have many underlying obligations, including informational obligations, to others. We cannot understand informed consent, the standards that it must meet, or the limits to its use, without taking that background picture seriously. Nor can we understand it without taking seriously the epistemic norms that must be met by effective communicative transactions. By contrast, the conduit and container model of information and communication, conjoined with the assumption that respect for individual choice or autonomy provides a justification for informed consent practices which can distort and mislead, supports numerous untoward implications and consequences. We believe that our strategy for rethinking informed consent both avoids these distortions and their untoward implica- tions and consequences, and provides a useful and coherent way of thinking about the importance and use of informed consent in biomedical practice. We realise that implementing the changes for which we have argued would require a massive change of direction in biomedical practice, and in the legislative and regulatory framework in which it is conducted. Some changes and improvements could be instituted piecemeal by medical and scientific institutions and professionals. Others would require action by various parts of government. A few might need better primary legislation, and in particular more coher- ent legislation for the protection of individual privacy. Philosophical work, we know, can take us only part of the way. However, it can at least take us part of the way, and there are many things that could be done. In the first place, we could stop Some conclusions and proposals 199 trying so hard to travel in the wrong direction. Rather than shoulder- ing the Sisyphean task of subjecting all aspects of biomedical practice to ever more exacting forms of informed consent, or persisting with fruitless endeavours to base all of medical and research ethics on an appeal to individual autonomy, anybody and any body whose work bears on biomedical practice could seek change. The NHS and similar healthcare institutions in other countries could stop trying to implement ever more rigorous and numerous informed consent requirements, and could remove requirements that are either dysfunctional or unjustifiable (or both). Research Councils and other research funders could stop funding work on improving consent procedures to make them fit for unachievable purposes, and could stop demanding the use of such procedures where they cannot or need not be used. Manuals for Research Ethics Committees could be rewritten to ensure that the point and limits of informed consent and the standards it must meet are clearly set out, and to deter inflationary elaborations of these requirements. Regulators could insist that it is communication to relevant audiences rather than disclosure and dissemination that matters. They could judge medical and research performance by the quality of the communication achieved, and not by compliance with informed consent protocols whose use cannot be justified. In the UK, medical and scientific institutions could open an urgent and unaccommodat- ing dialogue with the Information Commissioner, in the hope of securing agreement on an interpretation of the Data Protection Act 1998 for biomedical practice that supports justifiable rather than illusory conceptions of privacy (and similar points apply for other jurisdictions with similar data protection legislation). Patient support groups could insist on forms of accountability that support rather than undermine the intelligent placing and refusal of trust by patients, and could challenge regulatory demands that impose dys-
[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]
zanotowane.pldoc.pisz.plpdf.pisz.plblacksoulman.xlx.pl
|